The Rise of Rigor in the Calculus

Sdílet
Vložit
  • čas přidán 2. 07. 2024
  • Joel David Hamkins, Professor of Logic, Oxford University
    This lecture is based on chapter 2 of my book, Lectures on the Philosophy of Mathematics, published with MIT Press, mitpress.mit.edu/books/lectur....
    Lecture 2. The Rise of Rigor in the Calculus
    Let us consider the problem of mathematical rigor in the development of the calculus. Informal continuity concepts and the use of infinitesimals ultimately gave way to the epsilon-delta limit concept, which secured a more rigorous foundation while also enlarging our conceptual vocabulary, enabling us to express more refined notions, such as uniform continuity, equicontinuity, and uniform convergence. Nonstandard analysis resurrected the infinitesimals on a more secure foundation, providing a parallel development of the subject. Meanwhile, increasing abstraction emerged in the function concept, which we shall illustrate with the Devil's staircase, space-filling curves, and the Conway base 13 function. Finally, does the indispensability of mathematics for science ground mathematical truth? Fictionalism puts this in question.
    See lecture course information, including the schedule of topics, at jdh.hamkins.org/lectures-on-th....
  • Věda a technologie

Komentáře • 52

  • @rodrigozepeda2502
    @rodrigozepeda2502 Před 3 lety +13

    Thank you for making this lectures public!!!

  • @joeldavidhamkins5484
    @joeldavidhamkins5484  Před 3 lety +11

    Errata
    At 1:02:25, I should have said that it is the *complement* of the Cantor set that has full measure. The Cantor set is what remains after omitting all those middle-thirds sections.

  • @atlas4074
    @atlas4074 Před 28 dny

    On continuous induction at 37:20, this can be extended to connected topological spaces, and linear orders are connected only if they are dense orders with the least upper bound property. The more general versions states that if A is non-empty, whenever x is in A there's a neighbourhood of x contained in A (i.e. A is open), and whenever V is an open subset of A then A contains the boundary of V, A is the whole, connected space. The last condition is like saying 'if points arbitrarily close to x are in A, then x is in A.' The second and third properties tell you A is both open and closed, which in connected spaces means A is empty or the whole space.

  • @simohunt
    @simohunt Před rokem +2

    I have no idea of where you intended at pitching the level of these lectures at but as a 46 year old accountant with a decent level of physics knowledge I found them perfect. Thank you.

  • @rahibrehman4245
    @rahibrehman4245 Před 2 lety +3

    These lectures are awesome!

  • @antoniostojanovski9008
    @antoniostojanovski9008 Před 3 lety +3

    Thank you very much for your lessons,they are amazing

  • @NathanWHill
    @NathanWHill Před 2 lety +1

    When I was an undergrad I wanted to learn about the hyper reals and no one would talk to me about them. As a consequence I'm very grateful for you putting this out.

  • @leanhdung1994
    @leanhdung1994 Před 3 lety +2

    Thank you Sir!

  • @NikolajKuntner
    @NikolajKuntner Před 3 lety +5

    The inevitability of a function concept makes one wonder whether there aren't solid foundations that take such a notion as a primitive. Whether it be category theory, computational calculi or von Neumann set theory-like frameworks... The proposals generally appear to be either less workable or much harder to grasp than the theories that start with sets, types or domains of discourses. Maybe I have that impression because extensionality for sets is a simple starting points and other, younger concepts try to broaden this notion of equality.

  • @RenRealism
    @RenRealism Před 2 lety +2

    Nice lecture!

  • @ndmath
    @ndmath Před 3 lety +2

    Thanks!

  • @PhillipRhodes
    @PhillipRhodes Před 2 měsíci

    Holy shit. I thought I (sorta) understood Epison-Delta, but it wasn't until I saw your diagram at around 05:11 that I think I *really* got it. That one diagram was worth the price of these videos. Oh, wait... still, you get my point. 🙂

  • @luyombojonathan6688
    @luyombojonathan6688 Před 5 měsíci

    Thanks alot

  • @columbus8myhw
    @columbus8myhw Před 2 lety +1

    Continuous induction basically says, "if you're nonempty, open, and closed, and your universe is connected, you're the whole universe!"

  • @StephenPaulKing
    @StephenPaulKing Před 7 měsíci +1

    What downsides might obtain by taking delta to be nilpotent?

  • @columbus8myhw
    @columbus8myhw Před 2 lety +3

    I read a nonstandard analysis textbook ages ago. I remember being very impressed, but eventually decided that on some level it mostly amounted to swapping some notation out for other notation (replacing lim with st and so on).
    Reading about Nelson's IST was a trip, though. (Adding nonstandard stuff to the entire set-theoretic universe!) And I remember exclaiming "Induction is broken!" after realizing that, in axiomatic first-order logic, you can only require that induction works for properties that are definable in your language, and you can break it simply by introducing a new thing to your language. (Eg 0 is standard, and if n is standard then n+1 is standard, but we can't prove that all n are standard because induction is only an axiom for things that are defined without the word "standard")

    • @schmetterling4477
      @schmetterling4477 Před rokem

      Yes, but in practice absolutely nobody of importance cares. Not the engineers, not the physicists and not even the majority of mathematicians. This is trivial early 20th century stuff and it makes no difference whatsoever for people who are studying actual problems in calculus, functional analysis, differential equations or differential geometry.

    • @columbus8myhw
      @columbus8myhw Před rokem +1

      @@schmetterling4477 New tools open up new modes of thinking, even if they're niche.

    • @schmetterling4477
      @schmetterling4477 Před rokem

      @@columbus8myhw The solution to a differential equation simply doesn't depend on nitty-gritty stuff like nonstandard calculus.

    • @columbus8myhw
      @columbus8myhw Před rokem

      @@schmetterling4477 Correct. They are provably equivalent. ("Provably" meaning "there is a proof that they are equivalent")

    • @schmetterling4477
      @schmetterling4477 Před rokem

      @@columbus8myhw Then whoever came up with it simply reinvented the wheel and you can pick up your mathematics Nobel at the nearest car wash to you.

  • @dimitardimitrakov2841
    @dimitardimitrakov2841 Před měsícem

    I am listening on my laptop full volume and somehow struggle to hear. May be it's a good idea if you can edit the video and raise the volume up a bit

  • @rsm3t
    @rsm3t Před 3 lety +3

    For the problem at 34:00, is it functions with no isolated points? I don't know if this property has a name.

    • @joeldavidhamkins5484
      @joeldavidhamkins5484  Před 2 lety +2

      Yes! The third statement requires that every point on the graph is a limit point of the graph of the function.

  • @ryanj748
    @ryanj748 Před 2 lety +1

    About the definition at 33:45--does the definition say that there exists a dense subset D of the domain of f such that the restriction of f to D is continuous?

    • @joeldavidhamkins5484
      @joeldavidhamkins5484  Před 2 lety

      This is not quite strong enough. The third property asserts that every point on the graph of the function is a limit of other points on the graph. So if you change the value of a continuous function at one point, it would have your property, but not the property I stated.

  • @Achrononmaster
    @Achrononmaster Před 24 dny

    @1:21:00 who is your colleague in New York? Carl ????

  • @evangorstein4345
    @evangorstein4345 Před 3 lety +1

    Is the statement at 33:58 another definition of continuity?

    • @joeldavidhamkins5484
      @joeldavidhamkins5484  Před 3 lety

      Not quite. Although the continuity of f implies the property, it is not equivalent to continuity. There are discontinuous functions with the property. For example, the Conway base-13 function has the property.

  • @Achrononmaster
    @Achrononmaster Před 25 dny +1

    @41:15 The Asgaardians did one better than Yuen Ren Chao, they figured out the any amount of beer *_or_* mead is allowable theorem.

    • @Achrononmaster
      @Achrononmaster Před 25 dny

      And Abraham Robinson died of beer thirst because he only allowed himself a hyperreal ball amount of beer.

  • @mtgodziszewski
    @mtgodziszewski Před 3 lety +1

    It seems that the statement at 33:58 defines the class of Darboux functions, i.e. the functions with the intermediate value property, right?

    • @joeldavidhamkins5484
      @joeldavidhamkins5484  Před 3 lety +1

      Not quite. Although every Darboux function has the property, there are also other functions with the property. It is slightly more general.

    • @mtgodziszewski
      @mtgodziszewski Před 3 lety +2

      @@joeldavidhamkins5484 ​ Thank you, right, I see: we do not require that f(y) is a fixed value, but rather that it is close to f(x). An example is any bijection between the unit interval and the set (2,3) \cup (3,4). The image of the interval is not an interval itself. In the condition you ask for, the image of every interval is only dense-in-itself (i.e. with no isolated points), not necessarily an interval. But I do not know the name of this class of functions

    • @joeldavidhamkins5484
      @joeldavidhamkins5484  Před 3 lety +3

      @@mtgodziszewski These are the functions whose graph has no isolated points.

  • @jrshipley
    @jrshipley Před 3 lety +1

    I don't have the quote handy, but I'm sure there's a passage in Berkeley where he, talking about algebra (use of imaginary numbers, I think), endorses a sort of formalist, instrumentalist theory of symbolic significance (the sign gets meaning from the role it plays in a system of calculation, rather than from the idea it stands for). It's long been a project in the back of my mind to try to get to the bottom of why that was fine for algebra but not calculus. Anyway, I teach 5/5 at a community college, with little time for such projects, so if any of you young phil math hotshots out there can get to the bottom of that and write a nice article for me to read.... ?

    • @joeldavidhamkins5484
      @joeldavidhamkins5484  Před 3 lety +1

      Perhaps one possible difference might be that Berkeley thought the infinitesimal theory might be inconsistent? After all, he was mocking them for allowing methods that could also be used to derive nonsense.

    • @columbus8myhw
      @columbus8myhw Před 2 lety

      I suspect the deal was, it was not clear what the rules are. With i, we can manipulate it purely formally.
      (Various bits from nonstandard analysis, if memory serves, involve formally manipulating _quantifiers,_ not just pieces of equations, which is an added level of complexity.)

    • @scythermantis
      @scythermantis Před 2 lety

      @@joeldavidhamkins5484 Signs DO get their meaning from not just the 'role they play' but more the relationship between them and *OTHER* signs, according to Derrida; in fact, there *IS* nothing 'behind' that the signs signify; there is no 'signified', only 'signifiers'.
      See czcams.com/video/FtLMNcpgYEs/video.html
      Curious as to how Bennington and you would discuss this.

    • @Dystisis
      @Dystisis Před rokem

      @@scythermantis What role they play *includes* their so-called "relation" to other signs, which is a more vague notion that the notion of what role they play (in calculation and in general use).

  • @lunavicta4172
    @lunavicta4172 Před 2 lety

    33:35 For any x, there is a point y arbitrarily close to it such that f(x) == f(y). For example, if we had the following piecewise function:
    x != 0: f(x) = sin(1/x)
    x == 0: f(x) = 0
    I don't think it's *continuous* at x = 0 because for epsilon 1/2, no matter how small your delta, there are points within it with f(x) = 1, which is further than 1/2 from 0. However, there is a *particular* point y however close you like to x = 0 such that f(y) == 0, satisfying the condition that f(y) is within epsilon of f(0).
    Is that moving in the right direction at least?

  • @pensulpusher2729
    @pensulpusher2729 Před rokem

    Bruh I can’t even sort of read that chalkboard

  • @Maria-yx4se
    @Maria-yx4se Před rokem

    hank green but mathematician

  • @mtgodziszewski
    @mtgodziszewski Před 3 lety +3

    At 50:33 you make an argument that "we can give an account of - at least in simple cases - of abstract existence, for example to say what does it mean to say that the empty set exists". Can I ask what do you take to be this account? Is it some philosophical, semantic (extra-mathematical?) account? An immediate naive reply by just giving the definition "it is a set that has no elements" is obviously not satisfying, since it relies on the assumption that we actually can give an account of the 'existence of sets', which, if explained simply in terms of the axioms of some set theory (defining a notion of set), still leave unanswered the question of the existence of the objects of the theory - I mean, one can of course say that a set is any object defined uniquely by what are the elements of this object, which again opens the question of giving an account of 'being an element'. Therefore, do you take this account to be something along the lines of hilbertian or if-thenist theories that give an account of existence in terms of consistency along the lines of e.g. conceptualist theory, according to which existence of mathematical objects 'somehow' relies on human/rational mental operations, or something completely different?

    • @joeldavidhamkins5484
      @joeldavidhamkins5484  Před 3 lety +3

      What I had in mind is something like this: Whatever there is, we can consider the property that never holds---every predication instance fails. This property seems perfectly sensible, whatever one's ontological commitments might be, and this property provides a way of understanding what the empty set is. This account does not seem burdened with a requirement to develop an elaborate set theory of any kind. It seems possible to talk coherently about the empty set or the never-holding property or the never-true predicate, regardless of what objects exist and what nature they have. In contrast, to describe what it means for an object to exist physically seems burdened with all manner of complicating and quite mysterious issues concerned with the nature of substance and material. In light of the fundamental confusing aspects of quantum mechanics etc., there are very elementary aspects of physical existence that we cannot easily explain.

    • @mtgodziszewski
      @mtgodziszewski Před 3 lety +1

      @@joeldavidhamkins5484 Thank you. I completely agree that 'physical existence' is rather mysterious. But do I understand correctly that ontology of sets you would offer is that they are references of properties? Or what you say rather provide an account of 'simple' abstract concepts?
      Whatever the answer, would you say that there is also an easy way to give a (similar?) philosophical account of infinite sets?

    • @joeldavidhamkins5484
      @joeldavidhamkins5484  Před 3 lety +2

      @@mtgodziszewski I was only claiming the simple case. But of course, my belief is that one can carry on for quite a long way, including infinite sets, but of course, the account becomes more and more difficult, and therefore doesn't serve the point in the argument I was making here, namely, that some abstract objects (such as the empty set) seem to have simpler and more thorough accounts than physical existence.

  • @pinklady7184
    @pinklady7184 Před 3 lety +2

    You spell "rigor" in your video title. American English spelling. Are you British?

    • @joeldavidhamkins5484
      @joeldavidhamkins5484  Před 2 lety +5

      I am American. But having lived now in the UK for several years, my usage is mashed potatoes! My students say x, y, zed, and so do I, sometimes, but not always, and saying "parentheses" confuses them, so it is "brackets". And don't get me started on the issue of using pants as trousers!

    • @chonpincher
      @chonpincher Před 2 lety +1

      @@joeldavidhamkins5484 The typographical terms for ( ), [ ], and { } respectively are parentheses, brackets, and braces. Calling parentheses "brackets" loses a useful distinction.
      Another point: A "space-filling curve" can't be a continuous map from the unit interval onto the unit square, which is impossible. In particular, such a map would violate the conservation of dimension by continuous injections between euclidean spaces. What may be said about the given sequence of curves in this respect is that points in the unit square can be arbitrarily well approximated by points on the track of a curve sufficiently far down the sequence. Also, the sequence of curves exhibits a Cauchy-type sequential convergence (with respect to a natural metric) - without admitting any limit curve. Cauchy-convergent sequences are convergent in finite-dimensional euclidean spaces, but not in the space of continuous maps from the unit interval to the unit square.