Acceptance for Turing Machines is Undecidable, but Recognizable

Sdílet
Vložit
  • čas přidán 17. 01. 2021
  • Here we show that the A_TM problem is undecidable and recognizable, which is asking if there is a decider for whether an arbitrary Turing Machine accepts an arbitrary input. The proof is by contradiction and diagonalization.
    What is a Turing Machine? It is a state machine that has a set of states, input, tape alphabet, a start state, exactly one accept state, and exactly one reject state. See • Turing Machines - what... for more details.
    Easy Theory Website: www.easytheory.org
    Become a member: / @easytheory
    Donation (appears on streams): streamlabs.com/easytheory1/tip
    Paypal: paypal.me/easytheory
    Patreon: / easytheory
    Discord: / discord
    #easytheory
    Merch:
    Language Hierarchy Apparel: teespring.com/language-hierar...
    Pumping Lemma Apparel: teespring.com/pumping-lemma-f...
    If you like this content, please consider subscribing to my channel: / @easytheory
    Gold Supporters: Micah Wood
    Silver Supporters: Timmy Gy
    ▶SEND ME THEORY QUESTIONS◀
    ryan.e.dougherty@icloud.com
    ▶ABOUT ME◀
    I am a professor of Computer Science, and am passionate about CS theory. I have taught many courses at several different universities, including several sections of undergraduate and graduate theory-level classes.

Komentáře • 58

  • @EasyTheory
    @EasyTheory  Před 3 lety +3

    Thanks to my supporters Yuri, vinetor, Ali (CZcams) and Bruno, Timmy, Micah (Patreon) for making this video possible! If you want to contribute, links are in the video description.

  • @paolacalle5737
    @paolacalle5737 Před 2 lety +16

    I learned this two weeks ago and could never grasp what exactly the contradiction was until I watched this video! Thank you so much truly appreciate you.

  • @oribenez
    @oribenez Před rokem +4

    Finally, I understand it. Thank you for an excellent explanation.

  • @alphadal99
    @alphadal99 Před 3 lety +16

    Thank you so much man you are the best on youtube you made everything complicated easy. Much love from Portugal

  • @AkashKumar-lr6hc
    @AkashKumar-lr6hc Před rokem +1

    first time i understood the concept behind halting problem proof .. thanks a lot. 😄

  • @y.x3476
    @y.x3476 Před rokem +1

    Much clearly than anyone! Thank you

  • @betul3341
    @betul3341 Před rokem +2

    Thanks dude 👍🏻 I finally understood this part

  • @utkuceylan2309
    @utkuceylan2309 Před 8 měsíci +1

    You are a life saver man! Thank you

  • @dn6824
    @dn6824 Před měsícem

    what an elegant proof. i did not understand the contradiction before but it makes so much sense now. for context, i thought the contradiction was for all inputs to D. i see now that all it took was one input to D (namely D's encoding itself) to show why D cannot exist. thank you for the clear explanation

  • @madhavvyas3715
    @madhavvyas3715 Před 2 lety +1

    THANK YOU SO MUCH FOR THIS .

  • @conradhansen-quartey5053

    This ATM proof really helped me understand

  • @nickcooley8358
    @nickcooley8358 Před rokem +1

    beauty, was looking for this!

  • @momusic1427
    @momusic1427 Před rokem

    Finally I understand the contradiction . thanks man !

  • @eatyourspinachtomperez8700

    Very cool! Thank you.

  • @blaze9558
    @blaze9558 Před rokem

    Thank you so much❤

  • @amitozjatana4175
    @amitozjatana4175 Před 2 měsíci

    really helpful 🙏

  • @Patrickblox
    @Patrickblox Před 2 lety +1

    good shit mang thx so much luv u

  • @joserichorachmat8191
    @joserichorachmat8191 Před 2 lety +3

    So, in this case, the property of TM D (always outputting the opposite of TM H) is one we derive just for the proof? As is the nature of any decider TM to freely do so?

    • @KnakuanaRka
      @KnakuanaRka Před 6 měsíci

      What’s wrong with defining a TM that does that?

    • @KnakuanaRka
      @KnakuanaRka Před 4 měsíci

      What's wrong with that? If there is an H, we can use it to make D, and D can cause contradictory behavior, so D can't exist, and thus neither does H. Standard proof by contradiction.

  • @rasikaraja1840
    @rasikaraja1840 Před rokem

    Awesome 😎!!!

  • @superdahoho
    @superdahoho Před 3 lety +6

    but that's just the nature of D right?
    it always gives the opposite of its input.
    it just proves that a decider that does the opposite cannot exist, doesn't mean A_TM is undecidable.
    If you made D that accepts when accepts, and reject when rejects, doesn't that also prove it's a decider?

    • @KnakuanaRka
      @KnakuanaRka Před 3 lety

      I don’t quite understand what you mean; if you can make a decider for ATM, what prevents you from making D with it? If D can’t exist, then there can’t be an H that you can make D from.
      And what does the last part mean?

    • @barsbarancicek4138
      @barsbarancicek4138 Před 6 měsíci

      @@KnakuanaRka Well i am 2 years late to this conversation but hopefully i will get an answer because i am stuck at the same point. What @superdahoho means to say is D can not exist because it outputs the opposite. D not existing has nothing to do with it using H. So how can we say H cannot exist when H is not the reason for D not existing?

    • @KnakuanaRka
      @KnakuanaRka Před 6 měsíci

      @@barsbarancicek4138 The point of the argument is that if H (the decider for ATM) exists, then we can construct D, which results in contradictory behavior. Since we can’t have that, D cannot exist, which means H cannot exist either.

    • @kailanefelix2890
      @kailanefelix2890 Před 5 měsíci +1

      @@KnakuanaRka it doesn't make any sense!!! I'm with @superdahoho. I can't understand this proof bc the problem is with D.

    • @KnakuanaRka
      @KnakuanaRka Před 5 měsíci

      @@kailanefelix2890 The basic process is a proof by contradiction. If a decider for ATM exists, we can use it to make D, so D exists. Applying D to itself causes contradictory behavior (if it accepts, then it rejects, and vice versa); we can’t have that, so D can’t exist, meaning the ATM decider doesn’t exist.
      It’s a similar form of contradiction to the proof of an infinite number of primes. If there is a finite list of primes (a, b, c…. z), then you could multiply all these together to get P, and add 1 to get P+1. Then we can get P+1’s prime factors (p, q…); these exhibit contradictory behavior, as they are both in the list of primes (as they are prime) and not in the list (P is a multiple of every entry in the list, so P+1 is not, and its factors cannot be in the list). Thus P+1 cannot exist, so the finite list of primes doesn’t either; the list of primes must be infinite to prevent this contradiction from happening.

  • @pohloliq2122
    @pohloliq2122 Před 3 lety +1

    I finally understand it fully

  • @MEWOVER9000
    @MEWOVER9000 Před 2 lety

    Hey there, just a quick question. I see that you proved Atm to be undecidable, but how is it recognizable?

    • @alexm.2960
      @alexm.2960 Před 2 lety +1

      If M accepts w, Step 1 "Run M on w" will finish in a finite amount of time.

  • @owen5106
    @owen5106 Před 2 lety

    If we run M on w and it runs forever the first time, but will accept the second w in the language, how do we know its Turing Recognizable, if we never get to the second input? This is what im confused about.

    • @KnakuanaRka
      @KnakuanaRka Před 6 měsíci

      The second w? What do you mean?

    • @KnakuanaRka
      @KnakuanaRka Před 4 měsíci

      I'm not sure what you mean; the point is that the recognized emulates running M on w, and accepts if the emulation does. If M accepts w after some number of steps, so does the recognizer.
      So what do you mean related to the second w?

  • @nargesghanbari2340
    @nargesghanbari2340 Před 2 lety

    Tu es brillant!!

  • @otabekabduraimov5912
    @otabekabduraimov5912 Před 7 měsíci

    thanks

  • @hammadmusakhel5102
    @hammadmusakhel5102 Před 2 lety +1

    u r a legend, no cap.

  • @keerthi1504
    @keerthi1504 Před 3 měsíci +1

    We have *created* D to output the opposite..hence the contradiction arised. What if we create D such that the output is the same..it then does not create any contradiction. Please help..

    • @xufrank9945
      @xufrank9945 Před 3 měsíci

      I got the same confusion

    • @dn6824
      @dn6824 Před měsícem

      if you create a D s.t. the output is the same then that doesnt prove anything about L's decidability. you just found one specific case (out of an infinitude of cases) that shows it MIGHT be decidable. however, we want to find ONE concrete counterexample s.t. we create a decider whose output causes a contradiction on ONE concrete input. if we can find ONE specific case to contradict the claim (by assumption) that L is decidable, then our claim is wrong and therefore L must be undecidable

  • @shadowdragon2484
    @shadowdragon2484 Před 11 dny +1

    This argument is improperly defined. lets define D(f) = ~H(f, "f"), take a moment to convince yourself this is equivalent to what was said in the video. If we walk through the execution pipeline, first D is called with argument f. Then H is called with arguments f and "f". Finally f is called with argument "f" and if it accepts we reject and vice versa.
    Now lets evaluate the alleged contradiction case: D(D) = ~H(D, "D").
    Once again convince yourself of the validity of this notation. Here we can see the issue, an argument mismatch. In the execution pipeline D is called first with argument D, then H is called with arguments D and "D". Which calls D with argument "D" and the result is the opposite of that.
    I hope you can convince yourself from there of the fact that D(D) = ~D("D") is not actually a contradiction at all, that is if D(D) accepts, all that means is D("D") rejects.

  • @SunShine-xc6dh
    @SunShine-xc6dh Před měsícem

    Do the opposite is not part of h and is the part that breaks d. They aren't the same if h accepts h then h accepts h if it rejects it rejects the contradiction only exists in d
    Also running d on it code isn't the same as running it on its resulting output which can't exist without an initial input

  • @vimalathithand917
    @vimalathithand917 Před 7 měsíci

    Finally !!! I understand :)'

  • @storyofbo
    @storyofbo Před 2 měsíci +1

    For anyone still struggling with this here’s how I understand it.
    Assume you could know the number of ants in the world with 100% accuracy.
    You could definitely do that by getting all the ants and counting them.
    If you could get every ant that means you could definitely locate every ant.
    But it is impossible to locate every ant
    which means it’s impossible to count all the ants
    which means it’s impossible to know the entire ant population with 100% accuracy.
    The point is to assume the statement is true, find a smaller step that if done would guarantee the statement. Tweak that step in a way which would easily be allowed. Then see if it breaks everything.

    • @SunShine-xc6dh
      @SunShine-xc6dh Před měsícem

      Why is it impossible to locate every ant?

    • @storyofbo
      @storyofbo Před měsícem

      @@SunShine-xc6dh Looking at this now I don't think my explanation really applies to reductions since if I recall they actually work the other way around (Known undecidable reduces to possibly undecidable if true both are undecidable otherwise keep testing). But to answer your question
      It would be because how would you know when you counted the last ant? You would need to search the entire planet with 100% accuracy and even then how do you know ants didn't reproduce in that time, or maybe a spot you checked didn't have an ant and then later an ant you hadn't counted walked there would you infinitely check the entire planet with 100% accuracy at least with our current technology that is impossible. Therefore, the original original statement

  • @CLG111
    @CLG111 Před rokem +8

    How do you just arbitrarily say that turing machine D gives the opposite result? Why is this? There's no explanation as to why that is the case. This needs to be explained better.

    • @jmm5765
      @jmm5765 Před 8 měsíci

      If you run a decider (we assumed M) on an input, it will either accept OR reject, nothing else. And so when D runs M it gets a result back from it, either "accept" or "reject". You can then invert this result. The easiest way would be to use binary. Let's assume if M accepts, it outputs a 1, if it rejects, it outputs a 0. What we do is that after M has ran, we can have D look at the output and if it's a 1, D itself outputs a 0, and if it's 0, D itself outputs a 1. Does this make sense?

    • @gobwinning
      @gobwinning Před 7 měsíci +3

      @@jmm5765but isnt that kind of "forcing" a contradiction? How would it be different from using a decidable language i.e. the Acceptance DFA and outputting the opposite result of that/claiming it's a contradiction?

    • @jmm5765
      @jmm5765 Před 7 měsíci

      @@gobwinning Well not quite, your scenario would be just inverting the input, which creates a machine (B) that inverts the input of another one (A). Each machine would still be consistent in its results, they would just contradict each other, which is fine.
      What happens here though is slightly different, by creating this machine D that inverts the result of M, you cause D to contradict *itself*, and that's where the logical contradiction arises.
      Does that help/make sense?

    • @kailanefelix2890
      @kailanefelix2890 Před 5 měsíci +1

      @@jmm5765 I'm having the same questions as @7ow1nn1ng, that doesn't make any sense for me. How does D contradict itself? And how do D contradictions implies M impossibility of existence?

    • @KnakuanaRka
      @KnakuanaRka Před 4 měsíci

      @@kailanefelix2890 Basically, the cause of the contradiction is this:
      The D machine runs H on where M is a Turing machine (determining if the inputting the machine’s code into itself is accepted or not), and then returns the opposite (accept if H rejects, and vice versa). So what happens when you run H on ?
      This would basically determine whether or not D accepts D. However, internally, this would cause D to run H (the same thing), and then do the opposite. So if H accepts in the emulation, it rejects in the final output, and vice versa.
      This is a contradiction; you can’t assign a consistent value to the output because the internal emulation would require the same calculation to give the opposite response. It’s similar to Epimenides’ paradox of “This statement is false”; assigning a true/false value to it would imply the opposite, so you can’t evaluate it.
      So if this can’t happen due to contradictory behavior, what went wrong? If D existed, we could easily cause this by running D, so D can’t exist. And if we had an oracle H, the steps to make D from it are pretty simple; in order for D to not exist to avoid the contradiction, the oracle must not exist, either.
      The oracle is the only weak point or assumption in creating the contradiction, as if we had an oracle, we could easily do the rest, so by proof by contradiction, it’s where we went wrong.
      I also find it convenient to express the whole thing in terms of programming pseudocode with more clear names, like this:
      Oracle (TM, inp):
      #Return true if TM accepts on inp, false if it rejects or never halts
      Defier(TM):
      return NOT(Oracle(TM,TM));
      #Does this give true or false?
      Print(Oracle(Defier, Defier));